Jeebesh on Tue, 17 Aug 2010 11:20:15 +0200 (CEST) |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
<nettime> A critique of nonviolence |
dear all, waves of euphoria and crisis crisscross public discourse in places like india in recent times. this is also a great time for lively debates and thinking. here is an essay by Sibaji Bandyopadhyay from kolkata. he is an scholar who comfortably traverses multiple intellectual and literary traditions. maybe be of some benefit to people in this list. warmly jeebesh http://www.india-seminar.com/2010/608/608_sibaji_bandyopadhyay.htm A critique of nonviolence SIBAJI BANDYOPADHYAY AhimsÄ paramo dharmo â this is one aphorism with which almost every Indian schoolchild is acquainted. From early childhood we are tutored to discern the symptoms of the pathological everyday we inhabit, taught to be increasingly protective of ourselves in a progressively more violent world, and in the same breath told that all sane Indians of the past swore by the creed of ânonviolenceâ. Offering, as though a therapeutic solace to the troubled souls of today, it is incessantly reiterated that ancient Indians were unwavering in asserting the ethical propriety of ahimsÄ. We are repeatedly reminded, the one singular achievement of ancient India was that all her sages, meaning âcustodians of peopleâ called upon to preserve harmony among different callings and thus augment loka-samgraha or âsocial wealthâ, condemned himsÄor âviolenceâ without so much as a demur. And, to refurbish this popular wisdom, the modern ideologues committed to it invariably hark back to the MahÄbhÄrata, the colossal work that within the tradition of Indian taxonomy of genres bears the title itihÄsa. With the express intention of affirming iti-ha-Äsa or âso indeed it wasâ, they cite selective portions of the MahÄbhÄrata. With great fondness, they keep mouthing, for example, the dictum handed out to Yudhishthira by grandsire Bhishma in âAnuÅÄnaparvanâ. The dictum, lilting in terms of lyrical cadence, makes the expression âahimsÄ paramo dharmoâ or âahimsÄ is the highest dharmaâ more weighty by appending to it expressions such as, âAhimsÄ is the highest form of self-controlâ, âAhimsÄ is the highest austerityâ, âAhimsÄ is the highest sacrificeâ, âAhimsÄ is the best friendâ, âAhimsÄ is the greatest happinessâ, âAhimsÄ is the highest truthâ (13.117.37-38).* Indisputably, there is a kind of critical consensus that itihÄsa places an exceedingly high premium on ânonviolenceâ. Also certainly, it is this uncritical or unconscious adherence to the same unanimity, which gives to the painstaking statistical exercise undertaken by Alf Hiltebeitel the quality of the unexpected. Alf Hiltebeitel, in his 2001 book Rethinking the MahÄbhÄrata, prepares a tally-sheet for the phrase paramo dharmo and demonstrates that out of the 54 times it occurs in the MahÄbhÄrata, it is conjoined with the word ahimsÄ only four times â and, of those four, one is contained in Bhishmaâs dictum quoted earlier!1 Even if we grant that frequency distributions based on quantitative analyses are by themselves not sufficiently strong measures of weights attached to values, Alf Hiltebeitelâs chart provides other information that have the potential to meet the deficiency. We gather from it that along with ânonviolenceâ and âtruthâ there is one order of excellence extolled by the MahÄbhÄrata, which by a curious twist of logic, appears to give lie to the truth of nonviolence. And that is ÄnÅÅamsya or ânoncrueltyâ. Moreover, and surely this is telling, although the expression ÄnÅÅamsyam paro dharma or ânoncruelty is the supreme dharmaâ features eight times in the MahÄbhÄrata, it is only very recently that scholars have begun to take cognizance of ÄnÅÅamsya as a complex concept on its own right. Mukund Lath, in his path-blazing 1987 article on the term has gone so far as to say, âIt has been kind of voyage of discovery for me, to understand what ÄnÅÅamsya means in the MahÄbhÄrataâ [It is more so because] outside the MahÄbhÄrata, whether in the literature preceding the MahÄbhÄrata or following it, the word hardly has the supreme significance [as] it has in the epicâ.2 The obvious questions that this observation gives rise to are: (a) What is the ideological role of ÄnÅÅamsya in the MahÄbhÄrata? (b) Does it have any relevance beyond the framework of itihÄsa? In the justly famous dialogue between Yudhishthira and Dharma, the highest authority on the meaning of Good-ness, appearing as a Yaksha in the âÃraÅyakaparvanâ, the philosophical Yudhishthiraâs response to Yakshaâs question, âWhat is the greatest virtue in the world?â was, ÄnÅÅamsyam paro dharmo, âabsence of cruelty is the highest virtueâ (3. 297.54-55 and 3. 297.71). In the course of the interrogation which took in its stride such intriguing existential issues as âthe substance of selfâ, âthe meaning of happinessâ, âthe surest path of acquiring authentic knowledgeâ, âthe problem of recognizing oneâs own mortalityâ, the statement ÄnÅÅamsyam paro dharma comes twice. The fact that Yudhishthira the DharmarÄja chose to conclude the session by stating it once again gives to the expression the air of a well-considered maxim (3.297.11-298.22). It surely is instructive that the person most sensitive and upright among the chief protagonists of the MahÄbhÄrata, the one hero compulsively obsessed with intricacies involving moral conundrums, should choose to mark ânoncrueltyâ and not ânonviolenceâ as the ultimate humane attribute. However, the underlying assumptions behind the privileging is supplied not by Yudhishthira but by a fowler by profession â instead of DharmarÄja, they are spelt out by a SÅdra reverentially referred to as DharmavyÄdha. They are there in the lecture, rather lengthy and tiresome one at that, which the Dharmic Fowler delivered to a haughty Brahminin âÃraÅyakaparvanâ (3.198.1 to 3.206.32). Let us now focus on the salient features of the discourse on ÄnÅÅamsya spun by DharmavyÄdha of MithilÄ, the conscientious SÅdra whose very livelihood depended on killing fowls of the air, beasts of the field and selling flesh in the open market. Schematically put, this is what DharmavyÄdha said: 1. âAhimsÄ is the highest dharma, which, again, is founded upon truthâ (3.198.69). (Incidentally, of the four times we encounter the phrase ahimsÄ paramo dharma in the MahÄbhÄrata, one of them comes from DharmavyÄdha.) 2. But, even though men of learning and wisdom have advocated non- violence from the earliest times, anyone who thinks hard enough is bound to reach the conclusion that there is none who is nonviolent (3.199.28). (This same view is forcefully voiced by Arjuna in âÅÄntiparvanâ. The hero whom an immobilizing depression seized immediately before the commencement of the Kurukshetra War but who, thanks to Krishnaâs sobering as well as stimulating discourse managed to shake it off just in the nick of time said, long after peace had returned to the land, âI do not see a single person in this world who lives by nonviolenceâ (12.15.20). 3. Hence, the best way to resolve the paradox is to temper the exacting demands of ânonviolenceâ by emphasizing âleniencyâ or ânoncrueltyâ and, for all practical purposes, replace the commandment âahimsÄ is the highest dharmaâ by âÄnÅÅamsya is the highest dharmaâ (3.203.41). (In Mukund Lathâs words, âWhat the MahÄbhÄrata preaches is not ahimsÄ but ÄnÅÅamsyaâ.3 Lathâs claim is indeed provocative. Unlike J.L. Mehta, who believes â[MahÄbhÄrataâs] central message, repeated again and again, is that non-violence (ahimsa) and compassion (anrisamsya) are the highest duties of manâ4, Lath sees a distinct hierarchy at work in the MahÄbhÄrata â a subtle distinguishing operation that places ÄnÅÅamsya over and above ahimsÄ.) DharmavyÄdha reckons âstate of violenceâ to be an irremediable, unavoidable factor of âhuman conditionâ. By the same token, in his system of Ethics, ahimsÄ obtains the precarious status of an unrealizable ideal â it is as if, no matter how morally judicious a subject is in conducting his daily life, the goal of ahimsÄ can only be approached by moving along an asymptomatic curve that converges only at infinity. The Dharmic Fowlerâs axiomatic propositions â propositions that he himself claims to be part and parcel of authentic âBrahmanic philosophyâ (3.201.14) â lead inexorably to the framing of, what, for the sake of convenience may be called, a âprinciple of proxyâ. In the BrÄhmanic universe of the scrupulous SÅdra, the notion of ÄnÅÅamsya functions as a stand-in for ahimsÄ. It maintains a critical distance from both the components of the himsÄ-ahimsÄ or âviolence-nonviolenceâ binary without dissolving either of the two. It opens up a discursive space within which excessive violence is condemned and unqualified nonviolence considered unviable. Placed as a golden mean between two extremes, ÄnÅÅamsya gestures towards the apparently contradictory prescript of âviolence without violationâ. In short, given the fact that every being on earth is obliged to abide by certain violent but objective conditions, the only way left to man to differentiate himself from other living things and assert his specific species-being is to treat ÄnÅÅamsya as the closest possible approximate of ahimsÄ. But then, we are dealing with itihÄsa, a compendium of fables that has the extraordinary felicity of attaching contending signifieds to the same signifier. This flexibility may be bothersome; but, it often achieves effects that are overwhelming. ÄnÅÅamsya too has an indeterminate ambiguity about it. There are moments in the MahÄbhÄrata in which the word comes so close to anukrosha or âempathyâ as to make ahimsÄ and ÄnÅÅamsya not only mutually exchangeable (as envisaged by J.L. Mehta) but also to construe a general grammar of âethical careâ on the basis of ÄnÅÅamsya.5 The âfable of the parrotâ in the AnuÅÄsanaparvan is a case in point. On Yudhishthiraâs plea âI wish to hear of the merits of ÄnÅÅamsyaâ, Bhishma had recounted the legend (13.5.1-31). The story went: a fowler had mistakenly pierced a forest-tree with a poison-arrow; as a result, the tree withered away; despite the destruction, a parrot living in the hollow of the treeâs trunk did not desert his nest; surprised by this show of (irrational) attachment, Indra approached the parrot and enquired into his reasons for cohabiting with the condemned; justifying his voluntary decision on the grounds of âcompassionâ, âkindliness of feelingâ and affection for the erstwhile protector, the parrot invoked successively the concepts ÄnÅÅamsya and anukrosha (13.5. 22-23).6 The puzzle posed by the parable was, how come lower animals exhibit a sensibility which humans take for granted to be peculiarly humane. Indra wondered about the parrotâs supernatural feat of practicing ÄnÅÅamsya (13.5.9) and resolved the problem by adducing to the primary supposition of a (supposed) âNatural Ethicsâ. Indra discerned in the parrotâs behaviour a confirmation of the principle of âmutual careâ â there was no mystery; the urge to be generous towards others was a predilection common to allcreatures (13.5.10). Doubtless, the âfable of the parrotâ exceeds the limit set by DharmavyÄdha to the category of ÄnÅÅamsya. Similar exceeding can be found in other parts of the MahÄbhÄrata too. For example, in the almost last (significant) episode of itihÄsa in which Indra forbade Yudhishthira from entering the celestial abode if DharmarÄja insisted on continuing with the dog that had been accompanying him in his final journey. Yudhishthira was, however, adamant; he refused to abandon the humble animal. In expressing his touching loyalty for the loyal dog, Yudhishthira employed the word ÄnÅÅamsya (17.3.7); and, a little later, shedding the disguise of the dog, Dharma himself praised Yudhishthira for being thoroughly informed by the moral compulsion of anukrosha (17.3.17). Here too, conjoined as it is with a word etymologically rooted in the notion of âcrying out that "follows" (anu) someone elseâs "cry"(krosha)â7, ÄnÅÅamsya over- steps the boundary imposed on it by DharmavyÄdha. But, before one can cognize the âsupplementâ that âsupplantsâ any âsteadyâ signification, it is imperative to follow the âlogicâ of the âmain argumentâ to its end. Hoping that spots of confounding aporia would inevitably appear as we proceed and the spree for the free play of deconstruction would gather force, we mostly restrict ourselves to DharmavyÄdhaâs discourse in this paper. To trace the genealogical route of the term ÄnÅÅamsya (as explicated by DharmavyÄdha) most scholars refer back to the great ideological clash that took place about two and half thousand years back in the Indo-Gangetic plain. The two parties involved in the battle are generally known as the Brahmin and the ÅÅamaÅ â the former comprising the votaries of animal sacrifice and the latter men disenchanted by Vedic chants and the magical powers imputed to the act of sacrifice. Most of the ÅÅamaÅs â the two most prominent of whom were the Buddhists and the Jains â denounced the senselessness involved in killing innocent animals for either gratification or appeasement of the so-called gods. It was the dumbness of being cruel towards âdumb creaturesâ, a form of dumbness unhesitatingly sanctified by priests practiced in the art of Vedic rituals, which exercised them the most â the dissenting ÅÅamaÅs fleshed out their idea of ahimsÄ as a protest against this outrage. This, however, does not mean that all those anti-Brahminical sects which propagated ahimsÄ also preached that it was beneath the dignity of men to consume meat as food. The fact that the ideals of ahimsÄ and vegetarianism did not stem from the same origin but evolved along two different paths is borne out by facts like: while the TheravÄda school of Buddhism permitted its followers to eat flesh provided they were not guilty of procuring the flesh by their own hands, the Jain scriptures poured scorn on the TheravÄda ordinance as being an example of sophistry designed to camouflage the desire for the taste of meat â in contradistinction to the early Buddhists, the Jains from the very beginning favoured absolute prohibition on all meat-eating.8 While the Buddhist Emperor Ashoka (3rd c. BCE) is credited to have introduced virtual vegetarianism, the declaration in his First Rock Edict, âHere [meaning perhaps, Ashokaâs capital] no animal is to be killed for sacrificeâ, clearly imposed a limiting condition on the solicitous state policy governing the practice of vegetarianism.9 It is also legitimate to think that in the process of bringing about a ârevaluation of all (BrÄhmanical) valuesâ through the category of nonviolence â in the Jain-like exaggerated diction or otherwise â the ÅÅamaÅs reinforced some of the precepts which were part of the tradition of (pre-ÅÅamaÅic) UpaniÅad. The ÅÅamaÅic insistence on ahimsÄ certainly cast a new light on sayings such as, âVerily, a person is a sacrificeâ austerity, almsgiving, uprightness, ahimsÄ, truthfulness are the gifts [for that sacrifice]â (ChÄndogya UpaniÅad: III. 16.1 and III. 17.4).10 Again, undoubtedly, fighting against the home-dwelling BrÄhmins, the priests who had no qualms about earning their livelihood by gifting animal flesh to gods, the homeless ÅÅamaÅs could have garnered moral support for their irremediable wanderlust as well as claim a longer and nobler lineage than the himsÄ-epitomizing BrÄhmins from pre- ÅÅamaÅic utterances as âVerily, he is the great unborn Selfâ Desiring Him only as their worlds, monks wonder forth. Verily, because they knew this, the ancient (sages) did not wish for offspringâ (BÅhad-ÄraÅyaka UpaniÅad: IV. 4.22).11 On the whole, despite the earlier invocations of the creed of nonviolence, the BrÄhmin-ÅÅamaÅ hostility was scripted by treating ahimsÄ as the moot point of contention â and, due to that, what were before, at best, perfunctory and scattered, coalesced to shape a wholesome discourse. Moreover, such is the wholesomeness of the discourse, it still shows no sign of disintegration. PatanjÄli, Indiaâs legendary grammarian of 2nd c. BCE, had compared the BrÄhmin-ÅÅamaÅ hostility with the natural snake-mongoose hostility. Then again, while expounding on the âantagonistic compoundâ, PatanjÄli had instantiated it by referring to the âeternal conflictâ between the BrÄhmin and the ÅÅamaÅ!12 This grammatical wit is sufficiently incisive to keep us forewarned that the ancient ideological contrariety is yet to be transcended. Neither Mukund Lath13 nor Alf Hiltebeitel14 would face any difficulty in accepting MahÄbhÄrataâs ÄnÅÅamsya as a compromise formula â a formula devised to diffuse the disaccord between the orthodox Brahmana and the non-conformist ÅÅamaÅ. What is more, this view is quite palatable to many a radical interpreter of Indiaâs past, such as, Kashi Nath Upadhyaya, the author of the outstanding treatise, Early Buddhism and the BhagavadgÄtÄ (1971).15 None of them would contest that the concept of uncompromising ahimsÄ conceived by a section of the ÅÅamaÅs in order to morally nullify the himsÄ- oriented BrÄhminical practices provided the founding condition for MahÄbhÄrataâs ÄnÅÅamsya. Of course, there are dissenters; e.g., Chaturvedi Badrinath, the author of The MahÄbhÄrata: An Enquiry in the Human Condition. He wrote as late as in 2006, âThe three powerful words ahimsÄ paramo dharmo that [keep] resound[ing] in the MahÄbhÄrata âwould later become the cardinal foundation of Jainismâ.16 Nevertheless, if we leave aside the complicated business of arguing on the basis of historical evidence and take the softer option of deriving information from literary study of characters, it seems the first view has the greater chance of being vindicated. Take a look at the MahÄbhÄrataâs chief ideologue of ÄnÅÅamsya, the Dharmic Butcher. DharmavyÄdhaâs body is like a repository of various contesting predilections; it houses all but combines them in such a fashion that all real antagonistic contradictions seem to disappear: he does not slay animals but pursues his family-trade by selling the meat of hogs and buffaloes killed by others (3.198.31); he lays out chopped out flesh in the marketplace for the gratification of culinary appetite of his customers but he himself is a strict vegetarian (3.198.32); he subscribes to the theory of karmaphala but, (as though to negate the Buddhist-like semantic revolution of redefining the word karma to connote âpersonal intentionâ in place of âBrahmin ritualismâ17), insists that it is Destiny which calls people to their respective vocations (3.199.2). He readily admits that his profession is heinous but exculpates himself on the ground that he is a mere âpassive instrumentâ (3.199.3); he displays a great sense of discomfiture vis- Ã-vis the cruelties he daily practices but mitigates it by claiming that his steadfastness in observing swadharma or âthe duty of oneâs orderâ (3.199.14) bestows upon his job the benediction of ÄnÅÅamsya or ânoncrueltyâ; he appreciates the lowliness of his rough trade but it gladdens him to think that he supplies meat to âgodsâ (3.199.4) offered in duly conducted Sacrifices. On the whole, MahÄbhÄrataâs DharmavyÄdha, a rare example of a SÅdra trained in âBrahmanic philosophyâ, stands out as a person who to the last syllable of his being fulfils one of Manuâs kernel injunctions. In the very first chapter of his Book of Laws, Manu had issued the writ: âThe Lord assigned only one activity to a SÅdra: serving the other castes without resentmentâ.18 And, it is this lack of âresentmentâ (or better still of Nietzschean ressentiment) towards so-called natural superiors which enables DharmavyÄdha to simultaneously epitomize servility and make a case for âleniencyâ or âcompassionâ. It is, therefore, not surprising that playing the role of mediating middle term, ÄnÅÅamsya should come to the rescue of the Vedic Sacrifice, remove the taint of himsÄ ascribed to it by the ÅÅamaÅs. It underpins the rationale behind the new ârules of the gameâ chalked up by embattled Brahmanism, by lawmakers embarrassed by ÅÅÄmaÅic charges. ÃnÅÅamsya places, for example, Manuâs dictum, ââkilling in sacrifice is not killingâThe violence sanctioned by the Veda and regulated by official restraints is known as nonviolenceâ,19 on a surer footing. Clearly, the ânew wordâ20 which captures the imagination of both Mukund Lath and Alf Hiltebeitel, is rather about attitude than any concrete instance of violence or nonviolence â set up to countermand the ÅÅÄmaÅic over-valorization of ahimsÄ, ÄnÅÅamsya bespeaks of an âaffective stateâ. Encourages as it does to cultivate a sense of detachment to the consequences of his actions in the mind of the doer, the ânew wordâ bears familial resemblances with many Brahmanic and ÅÅÄmaÅic concepts. For example: in âÅÄntiparvanâ, after saying, âI know what ÄnÅÅamsya is, because I have always marked the conduct of good peopleâ (12.158.1), Yudhishthira heaps praises on a sensibility central to the set of precepts associated with the famed nishkÄma karma (12.164.41-46). Aparigrahah is one word that ÄnÅÅamsya recalls most strenuously. The word itself has a checkered history. Aparigrahah generally implies ânon-possessionâ. It appears in the ancient, most probably pre- Buddhist, JÄbÄla UpaniÅad;21 it is one of the âFive Great Vowsâ enjoined by Jainism;22 it recurs once in Chapter Six, Verse number ten in the BhagavadgÄtÄ.23 Mohandas Karamchand Gandhi â the apostle of ahimsÄ of modern India who on occasions looked back to Yudhishthira in his attempts to define the term24 and besides translating the GÄtÄ into Gujarati composed immensely influential commentaries on the book â was deeply impressed by the GÄtÄâs employment of aparigrahah. Lest we muddle up things, it is important to remember that aparigrahah or â[to be] free from longing for possessionsâ25 used in conjunction with thoroughgoing ahimsÄ connotes a value quite distinct from the one produced by its conjunction with the more malleable ÄnÅÅamsya. Being a self-professed âpractical idealistâ,26 Gandhi was often driven to reflect on the epistemological limits of the creed of ânonviolenceâ. A pacifist, he consistently disavowed the âdoctrine of the swordâ in his battles against imperialist forces. In pointing to the distinctive character of manâs species-being Gandhi did not, unlike the Dharmic Fowler, stop at ânoncrueltyâ, but said, âNonviolence is the law of our species as violence is the law of the bruteâ.27 He paid tributes to Mahavira, the Jain teacher who was among the staunchest advocates of the gospel of ahimsÄ, and the Buddha as well and termed them âsoldiersâ for the cause of ânonviolenceâ.28 Nonetheless, Gandhi maintained, there were certain aspects of violence which were âinevitableâ;29 he boldly asserted that his own doctrine of ahimsÄ was ânewâ, not âdependent upon the authority of [previous] worksâ including those belonging to the Jain school of thought.30 There are several passages in Gandhiâs An Autobiography or The Story of My Experiments with Truth (volume I: 1927; volume II: 1929) in which he expresses great fascination with the GÄtÄ and its English translation by Edwin Arnold titled The Song Celestial(1885).31 He took the GÄtÄ as his Book of âconductâ and sought to develop his idea of ahimsÄ on its basis.32 And, it is striking that Gandhiâs political lexicon is most profoundly coloured by a word which appears only once in the GÄtÄ, his âdictionary of daily referenceâ.33 That word, as Gandhi put it himself, âgrippedâ34 him from the start and as years passed by, helped him to forge his most original contribution in the field of social sciences: the notion of âtrusteeshipâ. The word was aparigrahah. Gandhi wrote in his Autobiography: âI understood the Gita teaching of [aparigrahah or] non-possession to mean that those who desired salvation should act like a trustee who, though having control over great possessions, regards not an iota of them as his ownâ.35 Note the crucial difference: while according to the Jain tenet aparigrahaÄ signifies renunciation of all material possession in the exact sense of the term, Gandhi derives from GÄtÄâs aparigrahaÄ the profile of a âsubjectâ who does not give up his private property for good but has the perspicuity to not to call anything oneâs own for the sake of public good. It may now be safely surmised that the concept of ÄnÅÅamsya has a positive bearing on itihÄsa as well as on modern history. The âsupreme significanceâ36 ascribed to it in the epic is doubtless absent in post-MahÄbhÄrata literature. However, its hidden intellectual career can be uncovered once we align ÄnÅÅamsya with aparigrahah and follow the latterâs role in shaping the image of the responsible leader of New India â a man gifted with both control over great possessions and the right attitude towards them; a man who affirms ahimsÄ but knows periodic release of controlled violence may be mandatory in the discharge of his duties. There still remains a serious epistemological problem. It is quite apparent that in pre-modern texts the will to himsÄ is equated to will to slay â it is assumed that even the most trivial act of himsÄ inclusive that of âspeechâ or âthoughtâ is grounded on and geared to the final solution of annihilating some other. Even when the Jains advised that it was advisable to avoid violence ânot so much because it harm[ed] other beings [but] because it harm[ed] the individual who commit[ed] itâ,37 the âselfishâ motive was dictated by the fear of damaging, in the extreme case damaging physically, someone else. Nonetheless, it seems, in the light of more recent formulations, neither the ÅÅÄmaÅic celebration of ahimsÄ nor the MahÄbhÄrataâs resolution of opposites through ÄnÅÅamsya nor the latterâs disguised deployment in modern political theory, evince sufficient alertness to the mechanisms of violence. A whole section of MahÄbhÄrataâs âÅÄntiparvanâ is devoted to Äpad-dharma, to the rules in situations of extremity when normal rules do not apply (12.129.14 to 12.167.24). Almost at the beginning of the section there is a sloka which is like a prelude to what is to follow. It says: âAs a hunter discovers the track of a deer wounded with arrow by marking spots of blood on the ground, so should one try to find out the reasons of dharmaâ (12.130.20). We are then introduced to a series of tales and counsels whose chief burden is to underscore the over-riding importance of âself-preservationâ. The instruction is: âSee the efficacy of self- interestâ (12.136.140). Therefore, recognizing instinctively that âthis body is my friendâ (12.139.73), a person should not refrain from doing things, no matter how distressful or distasteful they are, in order to save his most intimate friend; knowing that, âOne should keep up his life by any means in his power without judging of their charterâ (12.139.59), it is quite permissible and passable for a person threatened by imminent death to cause injury to others. (Incidentally, Gandhi too accepted the necessity of applying violence for self-defence.) This means at the moment of deepest crisis, the man caught up in it has every right to suspend all codes of formal behaviour orsadÄchÄra. More importantly, this also indicates that, in the ultimate analysis, the source of violence is always positioned as beingexternal to the body; it is taken for granted that the violence which may entail oneâs destruction is always inflicted from the outside; the terrible enemy is forever stationed elsewhere. This sense of exteriority in relation to fatal dangers also circumscribes the reach of ahimsÄ â to be ânonviolentâ then becomes a corollary and an extension of the urge to conserve oneâs body. It is no wonder, therefore, that Sudharman, a direct disciple of MahÄvira, in stating the irrevocable factum tenet of the Jain system, the first of the âFive Great Vowsâ,38 took recourse to the metaphor of the âbodyâ dreading foreign invasion and the criterion of âreciprocityâ. He said: âAll [bodies] are subject to pain; hence they should not be killedâ Know this to be the real meaning of the Law of ahimsÄ: as you do not wish to be killed, so others do not wish to be killedâ.39 Armed with this Law, Sudharman launched a frontal attack on the competing ÅÅamaÅ school of Buddhism and declared: âSee! There are men pretend[ing] to be houseless, i.e., monks such as the Bauddhas, [who] destroy earth-body by bad and injurious thingsâa wise man should not act sinfully towards earth, nor cause others to act soâ.40 Going by this extremist dogma, if a man lays down his life for any cause, say, for ahimsÄ, he does so because he willfully lets the other- directed himsÄ to fall upon him and not because desire for violence stems from his own body. MahÄbhÄrata too â the text, that in S. Radhakrishnanâs opinion is a stellar example of âreadjustmentsâ initiated by BrÄhmanism to process some of the objections raised by diverse âsystems of revoltâ41 â in substance reiterates the same criterion of âreciprocityâ when it teaches that the sum total of manâs duties is contained in the maxim, âThou shalt not do to others what is disagreeable to thyselfâ.42 However, complacency apropos violence can no longer be entertained. Among others, the psychoanalytic intervention in the matter precludes such a possibility. In 1920 Sigmund Freud published Beyond the Pleasure Principle (English translation: 1922). Sitting in Vienna, Freud composed that perplexing work just after the First World War ended and the Austro-Hungarian Empire had vanished from the political map. The two inter-related concepts he introduced in the book have radically altered all earlier visions as regards manâs aptitude for controlling violence. One of them was primary masochism and the other, death-instincts. At one point in Beyond the Pleasure Principle, Freud alluded to E. Heringâs theory that all âliving substance[s]â were subject to two contrary processes, one âconstitutive or assimilatoryâ and the other âdestructive or dissimilatoryâ. Next, with no prior intimation whatsoever, Freud suddenly took a mighty speculative leap. He substituted Heringâs âvital processesâ by âinstinctual impulsesâ and proposed that every living substance was âdualisticâ in nature â each was simultaneously motivated by âlife instinctsâ and âdeath instinctsâ.43 The expression âdeath-instinctsâ, later more famously known as Thanatos, makes its âfirst published appearanceâ44 in Beyond the Pleasure Principle â and, at the very moment of its debut it forces us to take seriously, perhaps for the first time in recorded history, bizarre hypotheses such as, â[There exists an irresoluble] opposition between the ego or death instincts and the sexual or life instinctsâ45 or âThe instincts of self-preservationâ are component instincts whose function is to assure that the organism shall follow its own path of deathâ.46 The death-driven Freudian psyche supplies the aetiology necessary for sociological analyses of âsuicideâ. But, it does more. Thanatos and the âprimary regressionâ called masochism together bring âviolenceâ to centre stage â the human appetite for self- consumption changes the meaning of âdangerâ to include instances that overstep boundaries set by the principle of âself- preservationâ; the sensational hypothesis that âpainâ can jolly well be a pleasurable sensation for the human animal, in effect, problematizes the ÅÅÄmaÅic doctrine of âmutual dependenceâ, the psychosomatic axiom upon which the pre-modern notion of ahimsÄ was premised. The 1932 correspondence between Albert Einstein, the physicist whose elegant formula e = mc2 provided the theoretical frame for making the atom bomb a practical proposition, and Sigmund Freud, the psychoanalyst who widened the horizon of âviolenceâ, unambiguously demonstrates that the latter in later life regarded the antimony of two basal instincts, eros and Thanatos, as one inviolable factor of âhuman conditionâ.47 So did the ÅÅamaÅs when they spoke of bodily pains and MahÄbhÄrataâs DharmavyÄdha when he said it was absurd to think that one could avoid doing violence to others in any absolute sense. In each case the theory is produced in response to a specific circumstance, each articulation is backed by a political intention. If the ÅÅÄmaÅic insistence on ahimsÄ, on according respect to all and giving credence to individual suffering was a strategy to mount an ethical attack on Brahmanism and MahÄbhÄrataâs ÄnÅÅamsya an apologia for Brahmanism, then Freudâs Thanatos was an offshoot of the brutalities regularly practiced by men during the First World War and the initial phase of Nazism. And, Adolf Hitler, the arch-ideologue of Nazism, in the concluding chapter titled âThe Right to Self- Defenceâ in his 1924 autobiography Mein Kampfhad written: â[just as] a weak pigmy cannot contend against athletes, a negotiator without any armed defence at his back must always bow in obescienceâ.48 On 6 August 1945, the allied forces fighting against the Evil of Nazism dropped the first atom bomb on Hiroshima and thereby officially inaugurated the Nuclear Age. With that strike, at one stroke man acquired a ânew attributeâ: âthe ability to extinguish all life upon earthâ.49 Replaces as it does the age-old diachronic order associated with âdeathâ by the possibility of the âsynchronicâ, by the ever-looming terrifying thought that man can actually make everything and being sign out all at once if he so wills, also brings to Freudâs idea of Thanatos or individualistic death-wish a quaint charm. It is in the historical context of the technological revolution which has the capacity of posing âutter calamityâ as the telos of humanity, that the real one feels, epistemological challenge of today is to re-think the question of ânonviolenceâ; ask again, what really is ahimsÄ? Footnotes: * All MahÄbhÄrata references are to the Critical Edition of the MahÄbhÄrata published by the Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, Pune. The English translations are based on (a) M.N. Dutt, The MahÄbhÄrata (nine volumes), Parimal Publications, Delhi, 2004 and (b) Kisari Mohan Ganguli, The MahÄbhÄrata (four volumes), Munshiram Manoharlal, New Delhi, 2004. 1. Alf Hiltebeitel, âChapter Five: Donât Be Cruelâ, Rethinking the MahÄbhÄrata: A Readerâs Guide to the Education of the Dharma King (first published 2001), Oxford University Press, New Delhi, 2002, p. 207. 2. Mukund Lath, âThe Concept of ÄnÅÅamsya in the MahÄbhÄrataâ, The MahÄbhÄrata Revisited, ed. R.N. Dandekar, Sahitya Akademi, New Delhi, 1990, p. 113, p. 115. 3. Mukund Lath, ibid., p. 119. 4. J.L. Mehta, âThe Discourse of Violence in the Mahabharataâ, Philosophy and Religion: Essays in Interpretation, Indian Council of Philosophical Research and Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers, New Delhi, 1990, p. 256. 5. Vrinda Dalmiya, âDogged Loyalties: A Classical Indian Intervention in Care Ethicsâ, Ethics in the World Religions, eds. J. Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, Oxford, 2007, pp. 293-306. 6. For discussions on the fable see: (a) Alf Hiltebeitel, op cit., p. 213; (b) Vrinda Dalmiya, op cit., p. 294. 7. For a detailed discussion on the moral implications of anukrosha, see Vrinda Dalmiya, ibid., pp. 298-305. 8. Sources of Indian Tradition (Volume One: âFrom the Beginning to 1800), ed. Ainslie T. Embree, Penguin Books, New Delhi, 1992, pp. 170-171. 9. The original text: â1 ShilÄnusÄshanaâ, Ashokalipi, ed. and tr. Amulyachandra Sen, Mahabodhi Book Agency, Kolkata, 1994, p. 144. For English translation see: Sources of Indian Tradition (Volume One), op .cit., p. 144. 10. ChÄndogya UpaniÅad, âIII.16.1â and âIII.17.4â, tr. S. Radhakrishnan, The Principal UpaniÅads, HarperCollins Publishers India, New Delhi, 1998, p. 394 and p. 396. 11. BÅhad-ÄraÅyaka UpaniÅad, âIV.4.22â, The Principal UpaniÅads, ibid., p. 279. 12. The VyÄkaraÅa MahÄbhÄsya of PataÅjali, edited by F. Kielhorn, Volume 1, p. 474, p. 476. 13. Mukund Lath, op cit., pp. 118-119. 14. Alf Hiltebeitel, op cit., p. 203. 15. Kashi Nath Upadhyaya, âChapter II: Section B: The Compromising Character of the BhagavadgÄtÄâ, Early Buddhism and the BhagavadgÄtÄ, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi, 2008, pp. 106-109. 16. Chaturvedi Badrinath, âChapter Five: AhimsÄ â Non-violence, the Foundation of Lifeâ, The MahÄbhÄrata: An Inquiry in the Human Condition, ed., p. 114 [emphasis added] 17. Richard F. Gombrich, âChapter III: The Buddhaâs Dhammaâ, Theravada Buddhism: A Social History from Ancient Benares to Modern Colombo, Routledge, London, 1988, p. 67. 18. ManusamhitÄ, âI.91â, ed. Panchanan Tarkaratna, Sanskrit Pustak Bhandar, Kolkata, 2000, p. 40. For English translation see: The Laws of Manu, âI.91â, tr. Wendy Doniger and Brian K. Smith, Penguin Books, New Delhi, 1991, p. 13. 19. ManusamhitÄ, âV.39 & V.44â, ed. Panchanan Tarkaratna, op cit., p. 129 and p. 130. For English translation see, The Laws of Manu, âV.39 and V.44â, tr. Wendy Doniger and Brian K. Smith, op cit., p. 103 and p. 103. 20. (a) Mukund Lath, op cit., p. 113. (b) Alf Hiltebeitel, op cit., p. 202. 21. JÄbÄla UpaniÅad, âVerse No. 5â, tr. S. Radhakrishnan, The Principal UpaniÅads, HarperCollins, New Delhi,1998, p. 898. 22. ÃkÄrÄÅga SÅtra, âBook II, Lecture I5: i-vâ, tr. Herman Jacobi, The Sacred Books of the East (Volume 22), ed. F. Max MÃller, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi, 2002, pp. 202-210. UttarÄdhyayana SÅtra, âLecture XXIIIâ, tr. Herman Jacobi, The Sacred Books of the East (Volume 45), ed. F. Max MÃller, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi, 2004, pp. 119-129. 23. The BhagavadgÄtÄ, âVI.10â, ed. S. Radhakrishnan, HarperCollins, New Delhi, p. 192. 24. M.K. Gandhi, âProblems of Non-violenceâ (in Gujarati: 9 August 1925), The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, Volume XXXII, The Publications Division, Ministry of Information and Broadcasting, Government of India, Delhi, 1968, p. 273. 25. The BhagavadgÄtÄ, âVI.10â, tr. S. Radhakrishnan, op cit., pp. 192-193. 26. M.K. Gandhi, âThe Doctrine of the Swordâ, (in Gujarati: 11 August 1920), The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, Volume XXI, op cit., p. 134. 27. Ibid,, p. 134. 28. M.K. Gandhi, âOn Ahimsaâ, The Penguin Gandhi Reader, ed. Rudrangshu Mukherjee, Penguin Books, New Delhi,1993, p. 97. 29. M.K. Gandhi, âProblems of Non-violenceâ, The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, Volume XXXII, op cit., p. 273. 30. M.K. Gandhi, âOn Ahimsa: Reply to Lala Lajpat Raiâ (October 1916), The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, Volume XV, op cit., pp. 251-252. 31. âI have read almost all the English translations of [the GÄtÄ], and I regard Sir Edwin Arnoldâs as the bestâ: M.K. Gandhi, An Autobiography or The Story of My Experiments with Truth, The Selected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, Volume I, Navajivan Publishing House, Ahmedabad, 1968, p. 100. 32. M.K. Gandhi, An Autobiography or The Story of My Experiments with Truth, The Selected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, Volume II, ibid., p. 393. 33. Ibid., p. 393. 34. Ibid., p. 393. 35. Ibid., p. 394. 36. Mukund Lath, op cit., p. 115. 37. A.L. Basham, âIntroduction: Basic Doctrines of Jainismâ, Sources of Indian Tradition (Volume One), op cit., p. 57. 38. ÃkÄrÄÅga SÅtra, âBook II, Lecture I5: iâ, op cit., pp. 202-204. UttarÄdhyayana SÅtra, âLecture XXIIIâ, op cit., pp. 119-129. See also, Upinder Singh, âChapter Six: Cities, Kings and Renunciasists: North India, c. 600-300 BCE: Section: Early Jainismâ, A History of Ancient and Early Medieval India: From the Stone Age to the 12th Century, Pearson Longman, Delhi, 2009, pp. 312-319. 39. SÅtrakritÄÅga, âBook I, Lecture I, Chapter 4: Verse nos. 9 & 10â, tr. Herman Jacobi, The Sacred Books of the East (Volume 45), ed. F. Max MÃller, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi, 2004, pp. 247-248. The same commandment is repeated in: SÅtrakritÄÅga, âBook I, Lecture II: Verse nos. 9 and 10â, op cit., p. 311. 40. ÃkÄrÄÅga SÅtra, âBook I, Lecture I, Lesson 2â, op cit., pp. 3-5. 41. S. Radhakrishnan, âChapter VIII: Epic Philosophyâ, Indian Philosophy, Volume 1, Oxford University Press, New Delhi, 1999, pp. 477-478. 42. Ibid., p. 506. 43. Sigmund Freud, Beyond the Pleasure Principle, tr. James Strachey, The Penguin Freud Library, Volume 11: âOn Metapsychologyâ, Penguin Books, London, 1991, pp. 311-322. 44. Angela Richards, âFootnote 2â, Beyond the Pleasure Principle, op cit., p. 272. 45. Sigmund Freud, Beyond the Pleasure Principle, op cit., p. 316. 46. Ibid., p. 311. 47. For a detailed discussion on the subject see, Sibaji Bandyopadhyay, âDefining Terror: A Freudian Exerciseâ, Science, Literature and Aesthetics, ed. Amiya Dev, History of Science, Philosophy and Culture in Indian Civilization, Volume XV, Part 3, Centre for Studies in Civilization, New Delhi, 2008, pp. 567-631. 48. Adolf Hitler, âThe Right to Self-Defenceâ, Mein Kampf, Jainco Publishers, Delhi, p. 572. 49. Heinar Kipphardt, In the Matter of J. Robert Oppenheimer, tr. Ruth Speirs, Methuen, London, 1967, p. 67. # distributed via <nettime>: no commercial use without permission # <nettime> is a moderated mailing list for net criticism, # collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets # more info: http://mail.kein.org/mailman/listinfo/nettime-l # archive: http://www.nettime.org contact: [email protected]